Philosophy 2700F/G Lecture Notes - Lecture 10: Mental Reservation, Consequentialism, Signify

56 views5 pages
Week 10: March 20th, Tuesday
Inquiring Murderer criticism:
You imagine that you are in your home one evening. Your friend drops by, saying that they are
being pursued presumably without justification or cause by someone who wishes to kill them.
They beg you to let them seek refuge in your home. You oblige. Some time later, the murdered
aies at ou house to iuie aout the heeaouts of ou fied. He asks: Ae ou haouig
ou fied? Kat sas i this ase that ou ae oliged to tell the truth (i.e. you are expected to
ase es o o, ad aot use etal eseatio – this is because, we have to presume, you
would otherwise be using the murdering as a mere means for the purpose of avoiding an
inconvenience to you or your friend.
Technically, there is a conflict here: beneficence to your friend vs. treat the murderer as an end
Kant thinks there can never be an irresolvable conflict when it comes to morality presumably, there is
always a correct answer for these dilemmas.
- Kant agrees with the idea of acting in self-defence in that case, you are not using the other
person as a mere means. So you could use the justification of self-defence in this Inquiring
Murderer scenario.
- Kant also supports capital punishment this suggests that he believes that at some point,
people lose their right to moral legitimacy (they can no longer be treated as rational beings). In
this ase, it ould also e oluded that the udee has o ight to the tuth.
*I think that since the murderer is not able to agree with the value of humanity in his
victim, it is likely that he himself has no rational nature or humanity thus he himself now
become equivalent to non-human beings, and can be treated as relative/subjective
The common-sense view, to man, is that of ouse ou should lie! Kat thiks this is og Note:
Kat appeas to e eisig oo sese. Kat addessed this ojetio i O a “upposed ‘ight to lie
fo Philathop – he concludes that the obligation of telling the truth is still more important.
- He reiterates his commitment to absolutism:
o To e tuthful i all delaatios is theefoe a saed oad of easo pesiig
uoditioall, oe ot to e estited  a oeiees.
o In addition, he says that in lying no wrong is done to the murderer himself; rather, the
lie is og, eause i lig a og is doe to huait i geeal: fo i lig I
otiute to it eig the ase that stateets i geeal ae ot [to e] elieed.
o He also says that, say you do lie to the murderer and he leaves. Additionally, your friend
also leaves out the back door, and coincidentally meets the murderer in this case, you
ae also alog ith the udee otiutig to the fieds ude.
*This is somewhat like a consequentialist ie; ut ol patiall sie he doest
believe you are responsible for the consequences when you tell the truth in that
ase, if ou fied dies eause ou told the tuth, Kat alls it a aidet
Week 10: March 22nd, Thursday
W.D. Ross The Ethics of Prima Facie Duties
Pia Faie is Lati fo at fist glae, o iitiall it sees to e… ut ‘oss sas that see to e is
isleadig; aodig to hi, the udoutedl ae
- Ross says that both Kant and the utilitarians oversimplify the moral life
o Both assume, wrongly, that there is only one basic moral principle (i.e. they are monists)
o However, there are a plurality of [basic moral] principles (i.e. Ross is a pluralist)
- Contra Kant, these are not absolute they admit to exceptions, based on cost/benefit analysis
find more resources at oneclass.com
find more resources at oneclass.com
Unlock document

This preview shows pages 1-2 of the document.
Unlock all 5 pages and 3 million more documents.

Already have an account? Log in
- Contra the utilitarians, there is more than one relation in which we stand to others
o Utilitarians agree that there can be exceptions to moral principles; they also admit to
some exceptions to even utilitarian principles
o However, they think that people have only one relation with those around them as
possible benefactors, or possible beneficiaries
o Ross thinks that there are many possible relations mother/child, teacher/student, etc.
Each of these relations signify different duties
o ‘oss thiks that thee is a highl pesoal haate of dut
Ross argues for what he calls a plurality of prima facie (a.k.a. pro tanto) duties. The view follows this:
- It is fine to lie in some cases (contra Kant), as would be the case in the Inquiring Murderer
- It is fine to tell a small lie to promote some great benefit
- It is not fine to lie however, to produce only a small (or personally beneficial) good (contra Mill)
Even when Kant and Mill get the right answer, Ross suggests that they get it for the wrong reasons:
The common-sese ie is that: oall poise-keepig… should oe efoe eeolee,
but that when and only when the good to be produced by the benevolent act is very great and the
promise comparatively trivial, the act of beneolee eoes a dut 9
E.g. Say you promised someone to meet them for coffee. But on your way there, you see an accident
happen. Staying and helping the victims will make you unable to keep your promise (to meet that
person). So should you break your promise and help the victims? Or should you ignore the accident and
keep your promise?
- Mill would say that it would be better to help the accident victims because it would promote
better outcomes (more happiness)
- Kant would say that it would be better to help the accident victims because you must treat
humanity as an end, in which case you are not treating the other person merely as a means
- But Ross would say that you must help the accident victims because it becomes your duty, since
your promise for coffee is very trivial relatively
Ross argues that there are five prima facie duties:
1. The duty of fidelity: the dut to keep oes poises ad to tell the tuth ou hae a dut to
live up to the expectations that you raised in others)
2. The duty of reparation: the duty to repair your character if you have committed a wrong
 ad  est o oes o peious ats. Fo , ou said o did soethig to aise aothe pesos
expectations of you so you have to live up to it. For 2, you said or did something wrong so you have a
duty to repair or make-up for that harm
3. The duty of gratitude: ou etu soeoes good deed toads ou, ith a good deed
3 rests on the previous acts of others [towards you]. If someone does something good for you, you have
a moral obligation (more than before) to do a good deed for them this person should now become a
priority for your good actions (above others)
4. Duty of beneficence: aiize pleasue, itue desiale oties, justie oes happiess
should be proportional to their virtue), and knowledge
*He ist sue aout hethe o ot people hae a dut to poote thei o pleasue o
happiness at one point he thinks we do have such a duty; but later he changes his mind
5. Duty of non-maleficence: duty to not harm; more fundamental and more morally obligatory
than the duty of beneficence
* If ou at help soeoe, at least dot hut the – mom
4 and 5 are general duties that individuals should carry out for those around them
There were initially 7 duties in total; but some of them can be collapsed together. So you have 5 overall
find more resources at oneclass.com
find more resources at oneclass.com
Unlock document

This preview shows pages 1-2 of the document.
Unlock all 5 pages and 3 million more documents.

Already have an account? Log in

Document Summary

You imagine that you are in your home one evening. Your friend drops by, saying that they are being pursued presumably without justification or cause by someone who wishes to kill them. They beg you to let them seek refuge in your home. Technically, there is a conflict here: beneficence to your friend vs. treat the murderer as an end. Kant thinks there can never be an irresolvable conflict when it comes to morality presumably, there is always a correct answer for these dilemmas. Kant agrees with the idea of acting in self-defence in that case, you are not using the other person as a mere means. So you could use the justification of self-defence in this inquiring. Kant also supports capital punishment this suggests that he believes that at some point, people lose their right to moral legitimacy (they can no longer be treated as rational beings).

Get access

Grade+20% off
$8 USD/m$10 USD/m
Billed $96 USD annually
Grade+
Homework Help
Study Guides
Textbook Solutions
Class Notes
Textbook Notes
Booster Class
40 Verified Answers
Class+
$8 USD/m
Billed $96 USD annually
Class+
Homework Help
Study Guides
Textbook Solutions
Class Notes
Textbook Notes
Booster Class
30 Verified Answers